Hanne Andersen
Copenhagen University
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Rachel A. Ankeny
University of Adelaide
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Mieke Boon
University of Twente
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Marcel Boumans
University of Utrecht
Erasmus University Rotterdam
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Hasok Chang
Cambridge University
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Nancy Cartwright
Durham University
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Henk De Regt
Free University of Amsterdam
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
John Dupré
University of Exeter
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Sabina Leonelli
University of Exeter
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Mary Morgan
London School of Economics
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Nancy Nersessian
Georgia Institute of Technology.
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Joseph Rouse
Wesleyan University
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Miriam Solomon
Temple University, Philadelphia
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Andrea Woody
University of Washington
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Alison Wylie
University of British Columbia
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.

Previous Organizing Comittees can be found here.

Chiara Ambrosio
University College London
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Justin Biddle
Georgia Tech
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Julia Bursten
University of Kentucky
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Manuela Fernández Pinto
University of the Andes
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Till Grüne-Yanoff
Royal Institute of Technology (KTH) Stockholm
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Catherine Kendig
Michigan State University
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Alan Love
University of Minnesota
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Matthew Lund
Rowan University
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Robert Meunier
University of Kassel
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Adam Toon
University of Exeter
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.
Eric Weber
University of Ghent
This email address is being protected from spambots. You need JavaScript enabled to view it.

Philosophy of science has traditionally focused on the relation between scientific theories and the world, at the risk of disregarding scientific practice. In social studies of science and technology, the predominant tendency has been to pay attention to scientific practice and its relation to theories, sometimes wilfully disregarding the world except as a product of social construction. Both approaches have their merits, but they each offer only a limited view, neglecting some essential aspects of science. We advocate a philosophy of scientific practice, based on an analytic framework that takes into consideration theory, practice and the world simultaneously.

The direction of philosophy of science we advocate is not entirely new: naturalistic philosophy of science, in concert with philosophical history of science, has often emphasized the need to study scientific practices; doctrines such as Hacking's "experimental realism" have viewed active intervention as the surest path to the knowledge of the world; pragmatists, operationalists and late-Wittgensteinians have attempted to ground truth and meaning in practices. Nonetheless, the concern with practice has always been somewhat outside the mainstream of English-language philosophy of science. We aim to change this situation, through a conscious and organized programme of detailed and systematic study of scientific practice that does not dispense with concerns about truth and rationality.

Practice consists of organized or regulated activities aimed at the achievement of certain goals. Therefore, the epistemology of practice must elucidate what kinds of activities are required in generating knowledge. Traditional debates in epistemology (concerning truth, fact, belief, certainty, observation, explanation, justification, evidence, etc.) may be re-framed with benefit in terms of activities. In a similar vein, practice-based treatments will also shed further light on questions about models, measurement, experimentation, etc., which have arisen with prominence in recent decades from considerations of actual scientific work.

There are some salient aspects of our general approach that are worth highlighting here.

  1. We are concerned with not only the acquisition and validation of knowledge, but its use. Our concern is not only about how pre-existing knowledge gets applied to practical ends, but also about how knowledge itself is fundamentally shaped by its intended use. We aim to build meaningful bridges between the philosophy of science and the newer fields of philosophy of technology and philosophy of medicine; we also hope to provide fresh perspectives for the latter fields.
  2. We emphasize how human artifacts, such as conceptual models and laboratory instruments, mediate between theories and the world. We seek to elucidate the role that these artifacts play in the shaping of scientific practice.
  3. Our view of scientific practice must not be distorted by lopsided attention to certain areas of science. The traditional focus on fundamental physics, as well as the more recent focus on certain areas of biology, will be supplemented by attention to other fields such as economics and other social/human sciences, the engineering sciences, and the medical sciences, as well as relatively neglected areas within biology, physics, and other physical sciences.
  4. In our methodology, it is crucial to have a productive interaction between philosophical reasoning and a study of actual scientific practices, past and present. This provides a strong rationale for history-and-philosophy of science as an integrated discipline, and also for inviting the participation of practicing scientists, engineers and policymakers.

BarcelonaPrinciples logoBarcelona Principles

The SPSP board has voted in early 2022 to endorse the Barcelona Principles, aiming to give everybody equal weight irrespective of their background, accent, style, or fluency in English.